Is Sally Free?

By Johnny Sakr

|

February 20, 2019

One of the most prominent objections against Molinism (and Divine Foreknowledge, generally) is the proposition that if God knows, and/or actualises a world, where He has decreed the path of human history, how is man truly free [in the libertarian sense]? This argument is made by theists and non-theist alike. Whilst this question, I’m sure, has perplexed likeminded philosophical/theological inclined persons at some point in time, it is by no means unanswerable. This article examines two arguments against Molinism (and Divine Foreknowledge) expressed in symbolic logic – (i) ¬◊(S & ¬S) and (ii) □(S→¬¬S).

¬◊(S & ¬S) & □(S→¬¬S)

The below ‘key’ will help those unfamiliar with symbolic logic to have a grasp of the argument under examination.

Key:

◊ – Possibly [Indicating that something is possibly, not necessarily, the case]
□ – Necessarily [The impossibility of an event not occurring]
→ – Conditional (If/then) [The consequence follows if the hypothesis is true]
¬ – Negation (Not) [The negation of a proposition or formula, rendering its opposite true]

————————–

Logical Moments

First Logical Moment: Natural Knowledge

God knows that if He places Sally in C she COULD freely eat a slice of pizza.

Second Logical Moment: Middle Knowledge

God knows that if He places Sally in C she WOULD freely eat a slice of pizza.

***God’s Divine Decree***

Third Logical Moment: Free Knowledge

God knows that Sally WILL freely eat a slice of pizza in C.

————————-

Is Sally Free in the Libertarian Sense?[i]

= Sally eats a slice of pizza

Argument One:

If Sally exists in a moment where S is true prior her act of will, then if she were to choose ~S, then you would have a world where S was true and then became false, which is absurd.

Argument in Symbolic Logic:

¬◊(S & ¬S)

Exposition:

It is not possible that S is true and then S is not true.

Defence:

The truth value of the counterfactual that Sally would eat a slice of pizza in C obtains its truth value because it was determined by the agent, Sally. It’s her act of will in these circumstances that makes it true that she would eat a slice of pizza in C. There are no determining factors outside the agent (including internal factors such as desires) that determine the truth value that Sally would choose to eat a slice of pizza in C.

For this reason, it is not possible, nor does Molinism argue that it is possible, that at T1 Sally would choose to eat a slice of pizza in C then at T2, this proposition is false because Sally chose to do otherwise. It is always true that Sally would freely choose to eat a slice of pizza in C. Sally could choose to not eat the slice of pizza in C [~S] but she won’t but if she did, then it would have never been true that Sally would eat a slice of pizza in C. Instead, it would be true that Sally wouldn’t eat a slice of pizza in C.

For this reason, Molinism is not hindered by the argument ¬◊(S & ¬S).

Argument Two:

One cannot change the past nor the facts. So whatever the prophet wrote must come to pass. That is, the prophet prophesied that Sally will eat pizza in C at time (t). What’s true cannot be falsified.

Argument in Symbolic Logic: 

□(S→¬¬S)

Exposition:

Necessarily, if S is true then it is not possible that S is falsified. Therefore, it is necessary that S is true at all times.

Defence:

Molinism does not argue that a prophet’s prophecy can be falsified. This is similar to God’s knowledge of future contingents, He cannot be wrong.

The issue here is the word ‘must’ – it’s not that the prophecy ‘must’ come to pass out of necessity but instead, it ‘will’ come to pass out of certainty. Although the prophet cannot be wrong, this does not mean that Sally is not free to choose to do otherwise. Although she won’t, if Sally so chose to do otherwise, the prophet would have prophesied differently.

Another powerful tool for the Molinist is Molinism’s functional equivalence with backward causation however, does not possess the problems associated with backward causation.

Molinism functional equivalence works as follows:

“Agent A can do non-B, even if God has fore[known] that A will do B, but at the moment in which he will have done non-B, it will have been true from eternity that God has fore[known] non-B.”[ii]

In the words of Kirk R. MacGregor:

To illustrate, suppose there was a multi-car pileup on I–55 just outside Chicago. In his middle knowledge, God knows that if he were to permit this evil event (because he knows he could work through it to bring about a greater good), then when the pileup would be reported on the news a few minutes later, a mother would freely pray that her son was not in the pileup. Consequently, in his creative decree God decides to actualize a feasible world where God permits the pileup but protects the son from the accident. But had God instead middle-known that if he were to permit the pileup, then when the pileup would be reported on the news the mother would not freely pray for her son, God in his creative decree may well decide to actualize a different feasible world with exactly the same history as the aforementioned world up to the moment of the pileup but where the son is involved in the accident. Hence even though I cannot change the past, through prayer I can affect the past. I can pray in such a way that had I not prayed, the past would have been different than it in fact is. Even though this is not backward causation (making the past no longer the past), it is what I have called in another place a “functional equivalent to backward causation.[iii] For it accomplishes, in a non-contradictory way, the aim of causally impacting the past without altering the past. The past cannot be altered, but the reason the past is the way it is consists in my divinely middle-known prayer in the present or future. Consequently, on Molinism, the past is not counterfactually closed, an observation Molina implied in reflecting on the scriptural truth that God knows the end from the beginning (Isa. 46:10).[iv] Through prayer, then, we do have some degree of counterfactual power over the past.[v]

In conclusion, I have demonstrated that it is not necessary for Sally to ‘eat a slice of pizza in C’ (call this ‘S)’ just because (i) God foreknows Sally will do S or (ii) God actualises a world where Sally will do S. Nor does it follow that if Sally has the ability to do other than what God foreknew, this would mean that at T1 it was true that Sally will do S then at T2, this proposition is false [that is, Sally will do ~S]. Rather, it would have always been true that Sally will do ~S.


Notes

[i] (i) Free from internal and external determining factors [internal or external factors may influence ones decision such as desires/motives [contra Jonathan Edwards]  and circumstances]; and

(ii) (Determined by the Agent [Agent Causation cf. Timothy O’Connor ] or the Event [Event Causation cf. Robert Kane ].

∴ Indeterminism

[ii] Francesco Piro, ‘The Philosophical Impact of Molinism in the 17th century’ in Matthias Kaufmann & Alexander Aichele (ed.) A Companion to Luis de Molina (Brill, 2014)394 citing Bernardo de Aldrete, SI, Commentariorum et Disputationum in Primam Partem D. Thomae, de Visione et Scientia Dei, 2 vols. (Lyon, 1662) vol. 1 disp. 23 (pp. 305–15), disp. 27 (pp. 389–406).

[iii] Kirk R MacGregor, A Molinist-Anabaptist Systematic Theology (University Press of America, 2007) 89.

[iv] Molina, Concordia, 5.19.6.2.1.

[v] Thomas P Flint, Divine Providence: The Molinist Account (Cornell University, 1998)  243 calls this type of power “weak counterfactual power” and states that an agent has weak counterfactual power over a particular truth if and only if for some event the agent can directly cause that event, in the absence of which the truth would not be true.

 

 

Share:

About the Author

By Johnny Sakr

Johnny Sakr was admitted as lawyer at the Supreme Court of New South Wales, Australia in 2014. He has completed his Bachelor of Laws (LL.B.), Graduate Diploma in Legal Practice (GDLP), Master of Laws (LL.M), Master of Philosophy (M.Phil.) (Law) and is currently undertaking a Doctor of Philosophy (Ph.D. (Law) at the University of Southern Queensland, Australia. Johnny is a former Roman Catholic, now Baptist – who adheres to the philosophy of Molinism.